Father of Atomic Theory | |
“All reality consists of hard indivisible particles, moving and colliding in empty space.” | |
Leucippus (c.450BC) | Theory |
Date | Person | Atomic View | |
Standard model Next to and along side of the development of atomic theory was Greek philosopher Empedocles' 450BC "standard model" of physics, in which the universe consisting of four elements (earth, air, water, and fire) and two forces (attraction and repulsion). | |||
c.485 BC | Parmenides (c.510-450BC) | Argued that vacuums are a natural impossibility, specifically that “nature abhors a vacuum”. | |
c.450 BC | Leucippus (c.500-430BC) | Often called the 'father of atomic theory', he was the first to conceive of the atomic theory, arguing that the universe consisted entirely of atoms and void, a theory purposely contrived so to contradict Greek philosopher Parmenides' earlier view that voids are impossible. | |
c. 420BC | Socrates (469-399BC) | Is said to have had a negative reaction to the atomic theory, which in his view was a theory which left no room for freedom of choice, and hence a basis of morality; this Socratic aversion (carried forward by his greatest student Plato), is said to been the reason for the two-millennium long interment of atomic theory. In short, the Platonic view rejected “mechanical manifestations of material atoms”. | |
c.410BC | Democritus (c.460-370BC) | Student of Leucippus, who furthered the atomic view, whose famous motto is: "nothing exists but atoms and voids." [9] Another version reads: "no thing is real but atoms in a void, and all things happen by chance and necessity." [17] In more detail: [1]“According to convention there is a sweet and a bitter, a hot and a cold, and according to convention there is color. In truth there are atoms and a void.” | |
360BC | Plato (427-348BC) | in his circa 360BC dialogue Timaeus, supposedly following Pythagoras, introduced the atomic theory proposition that ideal geometric forms serve as atoms, according to which atoms broke down mathematically into triangles, such that the form elements had the following shape: fire (tetrahedron), air (octahedron), water (icosahedron), earth (cube). This, however, was not atomic theory proper, but rather the four element theory. | |
c. 300BC | Epicurus (341-270BC) | Built on the theories of Leucippus and Democritus in the development his Epicurean philosophy ("eat, drink, and be merry, for tomorrow we may die"), that of aiming to find satiety in life's desires. He left his teachings in the form of some three hundred scrolls, which fell into the hands of his vicarious student Lucretius. In opposition to Democritus, he introduced the swerve of the atom theory, to allow for human free will. | |
c. 75 BC | Lucretius (99-55BC) | Student of the work of Epicurus, outlined the basics of atomic theory in his lengthy poem De Rerum Natura (On the Nature of Things), chapter two on 'movement and shapes of atoms'. [10] On heat in relation to atoms, Lucretius states: [2]“Clothes hung above a surf-swept shore grow damp; spread in the sun they dry again. On atomic volition he comments: “For surely the atoms did not hold council, assigning order to each, flexing their keen minds with questions of place and motion and who goes where. But shuffled and jumbled in many ways, in the course of endless time they are buffeted, driven along, chancing upon all motions, combinations. At last they fall into such an arrangement as would create this universe.” This talk of the absence of atomic volition, to note, is similar in context to the earlier circa 450 BC human chemistry views of Greek philosopher Empedocles, who famous stated that people related tend to mix like water and wine; whereas enemies mix or rather separate like oil and water. | |
c. 50AD | Hero (10-70AD) | Viewed matter as consisting of particles mixed with distributed vacua. | |
c.250 | Plotinus (205-270) | An anti-atomicist philosopher; view:“What motion of atoms can one attribute to the actions and passions of the soul? . . . What movements of atoms stir the thought of the geometer, the arithmetician, or the astronomer? What movements are the source of wisdom?” | |
“Nay, even that school which is most accused of atheism doth most demonstrate religion; that is, the school of Leucippus and Democritus and Epicurus. For it is a thousand times more credible, that four mutable elements, and one immutable fifth essence, duly and eternally placed, need no God, than that an army of infinite small portions, or seeds unplaced, should have produced this order and beauty, without a divine marshal.” | |||
400 | Augustine (354-430) | Argues: “let those philosophers disappear, who attribute natural corporeal principles to the intelligence attached to matter, such as Thales, who refers everything to water, Anaximenes to air, the Stoics to fire, Epicurus to atoms, that is to say, to infinitely small objects that can neither be divided nor perceived.” | |
Adelard of Bath (1075-1150) | Thought that physics of atoms made sense. [24] | ||
William of Conches (c.1090-1154) | Thought that physics of atoms made sense. [24] | ||
Thierry of Chartres (c.1100-1150) | Thought that physics of atoms made sense. [24] | ||
Averroes (1126-1198) IQB=170 | Had some type of Aristotelean-influenced atomic theory; later cited by Daniel Sennert. (Ѻ) | ||
1175 | Maimonides (1135-1204) | Refers to the earlier atomic views of Epicurus and gives commentary on the doctrine of the Mutakallemim (scholars of kalam), the first principle of which is that “the universe, that is, everything contained in it, is composed of very small parts [atoms] which are indivisible on account of their smallness; such an atom has no magnitude; but when several atoms combine, the sum has a magnitude, and thus forms a body”; the second proposition of which is that the universe is a vacuum in which the atoms are found; the third proposition arguing that time is composed of 'time-atoms'. [8] | |
(c.1288-1348) | Was critical of Aristotle; claimed that matter could be reduced down to elementary particles. [24] | ||
Nicholas of Autrecourt (c.1299-1369) | Defended atomism. [24] | ||
1417 | Poggio Bracciolini (1380-1459) | In January, while scouting about German monasteries in search of rare “humanism” books of antiquity, discovered Lucretius’ 55BC atomic theory based On the Nature of Things—all copies previous thought destroyed or non-existent—which he sent to his wealthy associate Niccolo Niccoli, inventor if italic script, a noted book collector whose aim was to will his final collection with funds into the form of Italy's first public library; Niccoli made more than fifty copies, in book form. | |
Desiderius Erasmus (1466-1536) | Attempted to reconcile Epicurus and Lucretius with Christian thinking. [24] | ||
1516 | Thomas More (1478-1535) | Attempted to reconcile Epicurus and Lucretius with Christian thinking; his Utopia was the result. [24] | |
1584 | Giordano Bruno (1548-1600) | Conceived of the atom as a three-dimensional physical particle capable of spontaneously moving itself. Using Lucretius as a basis, he extended the Copernican heliocentrism to argue that the universe is made up of an infinite number of suns with their own planetary systems; and viewed matter as following an active animistic principle, in that matter is ‘intelligent’, discontinuous in structure, and made up of discrete atoms or four elements (water, earth, fire, and air); proposed the view that everything that exists is made up of infinitesimal monads, of three varieties: God (the monad of monads), souls, and indivisible atoms. He was burned at the stake for his views; in the centuries to follow, his ideas were held up for ridicule, debate, or inspiration; Margaret Cavendish, for example, wrote an entire series of poems against "atoms" and "infinite worlds" in Poems and Fancies in 1664. | |
1601 | Francis Bacon (1561-1626) | In his 1601 essay "Of Atheism", on the subject of atheism, outlined the view that one can either believe in God or believe in atoms (or rather the "school of Leucippus and Democritus and Epicurus"), but not both. | |
1618 | Daniel Sennert (1572-1637) | In his 1618 Epitome Naturalis Scientiae he gave speculative support for atomic theory; in his 1636 Hypomnemata Physicae he outlined the view that each substance can be broken down into its minima naturalia a sort of atom, stable small corpuscle, or smallest possible component of a substance. [11] | |
1623 | Galileo Galilei (1564-1642) | Openly endorsed the atomism of Democritus and Epicurus, statements to the effect of which appear in Il Saggiatore (1623) and in Dialogue (1632), form which he drew a number of consequences about the nature of 'sensible qualities.' Viewed the atom as an unextended geometrical point. Expressions recurrent in his writings include: atomi ignei (igneous atoms), atomi del fuoco (atoms of fire), atomi calidi (hot atoms), and sottilissimi atomi (very thin atoms). [16] | |
1637 | Rene Descartes (1596-1650) | ||
1649 | Pierre Gassendi (1592-1655) | Wrote a book on the life of Epicurus, reasoned that to account for the size and shape of atoms moving in a void could account for the properties of matter. Heat was due to small, round atoms; cold, to pyramidal atoms with sharp points, which accounted for the pricking sensation of severe cold; and solids were held together by interlacing hooks. | |
1661 | Robert Boyle (1627-1691) | In his The Skeptical Chemist, argued that matter is composed of clusters of particles and that chemical change results from the rearrangement of the clusters; matter's basic elements were said to consist of various sorts and sizes of particles, called 'corpuscles', which were capable of arranging themselves into groups. First to apply atomic theory to chemical change. Defined an element as 'a substance that cannot be decomposed into any simpler substance'. | |
1714 | Gottfried Leibniz (1646-1716) | In his Monadology, he extended Bruno's concept of 'monads', in which universe consisted of an indefinite number of indivisible units, but defined such that each indivisible monad is primarily a center of force or action; he, supposedly, updated Bruno's concept of self-motivation of matter soul; with the term "force". | |
1718 | Isaac Newton (1643-1727) | Newton, in Query 31 of his Opticks, acknowledged the various 'atom attachment theories' in vogue at the time, i.e. “hooked atoms”, “glued atoms” (bodies at rest), and the “stick together by conspiring motions” theory, but believed particles attract one another by some force, which “in immediate contact is extremely strong, at small distances performs the chemical operations, and reaches not far from particles with any sensible effect.” | |
1721 | Emanuel Swedenborg (1688-1772) | Outlined a type of atomic geometry, in which geometric groupings of small, concrete atoms explain the properties of different substances. [14] | |
1748 | Gowin Knight (1713-1772) | His An Attempt to demonstrate that all the Phenomena in Nature may be explained by two simple active principles, Attraction and Repulsion, wherein the attractions of Cohesion, Gravity, and Magnetism are more particularly explained, which consists of ninety-one propositions, marks of an epoch in which attempts were made to push the Newtonian doctrine into molecular speculations; preceding Boscovich's better-known work on a similar subject by ten years. | |
1758 | Roger Boscovich (1711-1787) | Developed a ‘theory of point atoms’, a modified type of Newtonian atomic theory of inelastic collisions regarding atoms as centers of forces rather than as particles. His 1763 book Theoria Philosophiae Naturalis, outlined a ‘stationary atom’ theory, which reasoned that at short range, atoms attracted each other, but that at longer range, atoms pushed each other way, the latter aspect explaining gas pressure | |
1775 | Bryan Higgins (1741-1818) | Outlined an atomic hypothesis that recognized seven elements—earth, water, alkali, acid, air, phlogiston, and light—each one consisting of ‘atoms homogeneal’, being impenetrable, immutable in figure, inconvertible, and globular, or nearly so, and in which a speculation was made on the attractions and repulsions between these bodies. [14] | |
1787 | Antoine Lavoisier (1740-1794) | Considered bodies to be composed of particles, which were kept separate by means of caloric or the matter of heat, such that the more caloric there was in a given body, the more it would be made to expand according to Boerhaave’s law; he also introduced the modern definition: “with the word ‘element’ or ‘principles of bodies’, we associate the notion of the ultimate entity arrived at by analysis; all substances that we have not yet decomposed by any means, we consider elements.” | |
1789 | William Higgins (1763-1825) | His A Comparative View of Phlogistic and Antiphlogistic Theories, had developed a theory of 'ultimate particles' attached via divided force fractions, a type of atomic union to form molecules model; in 1814 he published Experiments and Observations on Atomic Theory and Electrical Phenomena. [14] | |
1803 | John Dalton (1766-1844) | ||
1811 | Amedeo Avogadro (1776-1856) | Calculated the number of atoms in a volume of gas, as defined by the Avogadro constant. | |
1814 | Andre Ampere (1775-1836) | Developed a ‘geometric model’ in which he pictured atoms of chemical elements as being composed of subatomic particles. [7] | |
1816 | Jean Biot (1774-1862) | Central person of the 'atomic theory' group at the Ecole Polytechnique, including Augustin Cauchy (1789-1857) and Simeon Poisson (1781-1840), who, in the 1810s to 1830s, employed models in which the atom consisted of a massive nucleus surrounded by an atmosphere of imponderable ether particles. [7] In his 1816 textbook on experimental and theoretical physics, he mentioned views on atomic structure similar to Andre Ampere’s ‘geometric model’ . | |
1826 | Gustav Fechner (1801-1887) | After translating Biot’s 1816 textbook into German, in 1828 he went on to construct a dynamic atomic model in which the ‘atoms simulate in small dimensions the situations of the astronomical objects in larger dimensions, being animate in any case by the same forces; and each body may be regarded as a system of innumerably many small suns, floating at comparatively large distances from one another, such that each or several of them together are surrounded by orbiting planetary atoms.” [7] | |
1841 | Karl Marx (1818-1883) | Completed his 1841 PhD dissertation on Differences between the Natural Philosophies of Democritus and Epicurus, in which he is very critical of Gassendi’s efforts to rehabilitate Epicureanism; also authored a post-humorous piece entitled “Epicurean Philosophy”. | |
1870 | William Thomson (1824-1907) → Vortex atom theory | | |
1871 | Wilhelm Weber (1804-1891) | Built on Fechner’s model of the atom, but assumed the heavy solar atoms and the almost massless planetary atoms to be electrically charged, replacing Fechner’s gravitational attraction with electrical forces. Weber gave the following picture of an atom:“Let e be the positively charged electrical particle, and let the negative particle, carrying an opposite charge of equal amount, be denoted by –e Let only the latter be associated with the massive atom, whose mass is so large that the mass of the positive particle may be considered as negligible. The particle –e may then be considered as being at rest, while just the particle e moves around the particle –e.” This model, supposedly, became defunct with James Maxell’s electromagnetic theory of transverse electric and magnetic waves. | |
1868 | Ludwig Boltzmann (1844-1906) | Building on the kinetic theory work of Clausius and Maxwell, developed the statistical mechanics of atomic movement (velocities), thus bring conclusive validation to atomic theory, over detracting views, such as professed by those of the energetics school, particularly Ernst Mach, Wilhelm Ostwald, and Pierre Duhem, who considered atoms to be a metaphysical abstraction. | |
1878 | Alfred Mayer (1836-1897) → Floating magnets experiment | | |
1883 | Henri Bergson (1859-1941) | Published Les Extraits de Lucrece (Excerpts from Lucretius) giving commentary on the atom-void views of Lucretius, a view which he favored. | |
1897 | Ernst Mach (1838-1916) | Famously declared: "I don't believe that atoms exist!", following an 1897 lecture by Ludwig Boltzmann at the Imperial Academy of Science in Vienna; often cited as the “last physicist to deny the existence of the atom”; Mach’s opposition to Boltzmann, along with his teaming up with Wilhelm Ostwald with the energetics school, is said to be what drove Boltzmann to the grave; Max Planck’s famous “a new scientific truth” quote is attributed to this debacle; Albert Einstein later met with Mach to see if he would be willing to recant, if he could predict a property of a gas in such a way that it required the assumption of the existence of atoms—Mach, supposedly, as Einstein recalled delightedly, “replied affirmatively”. [23] | |
1897 | Joseph Thomson (1856-1940) | After experimenting with cathode-ray tubes, published a paper, in which he postulated that the cathode rays are streams of “negatively electrified particles” [i.e. electrons] with mass. | |
Subatomic Theory | |||
1891 | George Stoney (1826-1911) | Coined the term "electron" (1891); also estimated the size of the atom (along with William Thomson and Josef Loschmidt) in circa 1870. | |
1903 | Hantaro Nagaoka (1865-1950) | Building on the 1859 work of James Maxwell on the stability of Saturn’s rings, Nagaoka mathematically considered the properties of a ‘Saturnian’ atom, which he supposed the atom to consist of a central attracting mass surrounded by rings of rotating electrons, showing that such a system was stable if the attractive force was large. [6] | |
1904 | Joseph Thomson (1856-1940) | ||
1909 | Wilhelm Ostwal (1853-1932) | Quote: “I am now convinced that we have recently become possessed of experimental evidence of the discrete or grained nature of matter, which the atomic hypothesis sought in vain for hundreds and thousands of years. The isolation and counting of gaseous ions, on the one hand, which have crowned with success the long and brilliant researches of J.J. Thomson, and, on the other, agreement of the Brownian movement with the requirements of the kinetic hypothesis, established by many investigators and most conclusively by J. Perrin, justify the most cautious scientist in now speaking of the experimental proof of the atomic nature of matter, the atomic hypothesis is thus raised to the position of a scientifically well-founded theory, and can claim a place in a text-book intended for use as an introduction to the present state of our knowledge of general chemistry.” (Ѻ) [21] | |
1911 | Ernest Rutherford (1871-1937) | ||
1913 | Niels Bohr (1885-1962) → Bohr model | ||
1924 | Louis de Broglie (1892-1987) | Introduced the 'wavelike atom' model, proposing that all matter, particularly electrons, must have a wave-like behavior in their motion. | |
1926 | Jean Perrin (1870-1942) | Won the Nobel Prize in physics for proving, conclusively, the reality of the “atomistic description” of nature—a recognition often said to mark the final and formal acceptance of Leucippus’ c.450BC atomic theory by science officially; he did this by calculating Avogadro's number using three different methods, all involving liquid phase systems. First, he used a gamboge soap-like emulsion, second by doing experimental work on Brownian motion, and third by confirming Einstein’s theory of particle rotation in the liquid phase. | |
1926 | Erwin Schrodinger (1887-1961) | | |
1932 | James Chadwick (1891-1974) | Experimentally discovered the 'neutron' an uncharged nuclear particle slightly larger in mass than the proton. | |
1955 | Erwin Muller (1911-1977) | | |
Subnuclear Theory | |||
1963 | Murray Gell-Mann (1929-) | Assigned the name "quark" to the fundamental constituents of the nucleon (protons and neutrons). | |
See main: Human molecular theory, Human molecular hypothesis, human moleculeA subset of atomic theory logic is 'human molecular theory', the premise that humans are made of atoms, ordered in specific arrangement, in the form of a dynamic molecule. The immensity of this simple doctrine cannot be overestimated in terms of it far-reaching implications. To illuminate, as commented, in aggregate form, famously by American physicist Richard Feynman, in his famous time capsule wisdom:
“If all scientific knowledge were lost in a cataclysm, the single statement that I would propose to best pass on our understanding of the world, so to preserve the most information for the next generations of creatures, would be: ‘all things are made of atoms’.”
“All humans are made of atoms”
Modern Human Molecular Theory | |||
1919 | George Carey (1845-1924) | Definitively stated that: "man's body is a chemical formula in operation." | |
2000 | Robert Sterner (c.1958-) | In their ecological stoichiometric studies of elemental composition variations in related species of small fresh water organisms, Sterner and Elser initiated modern 'human molecular theory' by calculating the following 22-element empirical molecular formula for one person: H375,000,000 O132,000,000 C85,700,000 N6,430,000 Ca1,500,000 P1,020,000 S206,000 Na183,000 K177,000 Cl127,000 Mg40,000 Si38,600 Fe2,680 Zn2,110 Cu76 I14 Mn13 F13 Cr7 Se4 Mo3 Co1 which they specifically defined as the chemical formula for one 'human molecule', thus giving, for the first time, experimentally measured proof or derivation that a human being is a 'molecule' comprised of a specific number of operational atoms. | |
James Elser (c.1959-) | |||
2002 | Libb Thims (c.1975-) | In his human thermodynamic studies, particularly surrounding efforts to understand how the spontaneity criterion applies to human relationships, in 2002 calculated the following 26-element empirical molecular formula: H2.5E9 O9.7E8 C4.9E8 N4.7E7 P9.0E6 Ca8.9E6 K2.0E6 Na1.9E6 S1.6E6 Cl1.3E6 Mg3.0E5 Fe5.5E4 F5.4E4 Zn1.2E4 Si9.1E3 Cu1.2E3 B7.1E2 Cr98 Mn93 Ni87 Se65 Sn64 I60 Mo19 Co17 V and in 2007 wrote the first textbook on the behavior and reactions of human molecules; and in 2008, after becoming aware of the earlier work of Sterner and Elser, wrote the first booklet on history of the concept of the human molecule. | |
2005 | New Scientist | In 2005, in an anon author of a New Scientist article entitled “That’s Life”, gave the following 12-element empirical formula was: [15] This attempt at what the author calls "one's chemical formula", however, is lacking in 14 elements shown to have active role in the internal functioning of a person. |
“When I taught physics in secondary school in 1891, the invisible and indestructible atom was the foundation upon which the scientific structure was built. Some of my naïve pupils were skeptical and asked if I were telling a fairy tale.”— Judson Herrick (1956), The Evolution of Human Nature (pg. 33)
“If, in some cataclysm, all scientific knowledge were to be destroyed, and only one sentence passed on to the next generation of creatures, what statement would contain the most information in the fewest words? I believe it is the atomic hypothesis (or atomic fact, or whatever you wish to call it) that all things are made of atoms — little particles that move around in perpetual motion, attracting each other when they are a little distance apart, but repelling upon being squeezed into one another. In that one sentence you will see an enormous amount of information about the world, if just a little imagination and thinking are applied.”— Richard Feynman (1964), Lectures on Physics